Uploader: Alex
Country: Bulgaria
Uploaded: Sep 03, 2018
Price: Free
Rating: Based on 1 user ratings

Please, verify you are not robot to load rest of pages

download sartre existentialism and human emotions pdf

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism and Human Emotions. “Existentialism” translated
by Bernard Frechtman. Remaining selections from Being and Nothingness
translated by Hazel E. Barnes. New York: 1985.
Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980) was a French existentialist philosopher. Sartre’s body of fiction and plays
won him the Nobel Prize in Literature, which he refused.
Existentialism.
This essay answers charges brought against Sartre’s existentialism. The main charges are
that existentialism promotes ethical quietism and that existentialism emphasizes human
degradation to the neglect of human joys. In this latter regard, critics charge that existentialism
conceives man as isolated, not bound in community with others, and that the existential ethic
permits all actions and condemns none.
Sartre responds that existentialism implies that all truth and action occur in human
settings perceived within human subjectivity. One source from which derives the allegation that
existentialism focuses upon human misery is raw conservatism; the critics believe that one should
never confront the status quo, but should excuse ill circumstances as unavoidable. Existentialism
emphasizes human choice. Circumstances are not immutable; they are frequently a product of
human election.
Existentialism takes human subjectivity as its starting point. Existence precedes essence,
that is, the individual human consciousness logically precedes the reality of the world. The
individual comes first, defines himself, and then examines the world, his context. There is no god,
no objective viewpoint outside the individual’s perspective. Man invents himself. Therefore, man
is wholly responsible for his circumstance and that of others. What we choose, we call good. By
the term “good,” we imply that our choice is good for all others.
Critics focus on core words in existentialism: anguish, forlornness, and despair. By
“anguish,” Sartre means the feeling that arises when one recognizes that her choices legislate for
all mankind, and she is responsible. By “forlornness,” Sartre asserts that god does not exist, and
one must face up to the many implications of this fact. Morality lacks force, and man loses his
way. There is nothing within or without stable enough to grasp. People are free, utterly. Ethical
principles are too generalized; one must trust his instincts. One’s feelings follow the train of one’s
acts. By “despair,” Sartre means that prayer doesn’t work. One must confine oneself to what one
can do and the probabilities that make those actions possible. God will not be intervening to
assist.
Sartre says of the charge that existentialism promotes ethical quietism that existentialism
entails realistic action. Man is his actions and life becomes what men make it. What critics take
for pessimism in existentialists is at bottom a gritty optimism.
Sartre answers the charge that existentialism distorts man by considering him in isolation
from others. Descartes’s cogito ergo sum is the rudimentary truth of human life; we come to exist
as we recognize subjectively that we are existing. When we realize that we exist, we are
positioned to recognize the existence of others. While there is no fixed human nature, there is a
universal human condition: all humans are born, work in the world with others, and die. So,
every individual has value, that is, every individual implies the existence of other individuals. As
such, all human experience may be understood by others.
Sartre answers the criticism that existentialism authorizes every person to do whatever he
chooses, and offers no yardstick by which to judge human actions. To be free is to be absolute.
Even not choosing is choice. Moral choice is akin to creating art, and an individual is an artwork
of his own making. Man’s ethical choices define the individual; the world is so structured that one
cannot fail to choose an ethical stance. As to moral yardsticks, Sartre asserts he does not believe
in progress. Mankind does not change. Circumstances change, but human choice endures. The
choices of others may not be morally condemned, but they may be identified as errors. A person
who makes excuses is dishonest; he denies his absolute freedom. And wanting absolute freedom
for oneself, one can only want it for others as well. Sartre asserts that since he has rejected God as
purveyor of values, someone has to make them up. Human life has no essential meaning. Human
meaning is chosen by humans.
Epitome by Brad Lancaster, © 2011. Website: lancasterlawoffice.com
Page 1 of 2.
Sartre concludes that existentialism is nothing more than consistent atheism. If God
exists, it would not matter.
Freedom and Responsibility.
This fragment from Being and Nothingness explains the implications of the freedom of
the for-itself (which is consciousness without god). Absolute freedom means that the individual is
absolutely responsible. Whatever happens to me or others is something of the individual’s
creation. There are no accidents. If one elects not to commit suicide in the face of unwanted
outcomes, then one has chosen the outcome. Human existence stands therefore without excuses.
Though it appears that some facts are outside the individual’s control (for example, one’s birth),
the individual nevertheless knows nothing of such facts. He becomes an individual by adopting
such “facts” into his choices. The individual lives and exists only in the present. Anguish arises
when the individual recognizes that her choices touch the world, which is a peopled world. She
sees that her existence affects everything outside herself. Most individuals “flee anguish in bad
faith.”
The Desire to Be God.
These two fragments from Being and Nothingness describe the existentialist view of the
psychological origin of god myths. Every individual is a unique project of creating himself. That
project is a motivation to self-define, which involves himself, the physical world, the Other, and a
striving toward unification of these aspects.
Every individual’s project (which constitutes that individual) is to be God. The idea of
god describes the limit of the individual self-constituting project. To undertake the personforming project, oddly, involves nihilation, because desire empties being. The free man empties
himself in favor of choice. Desire for being, however, is that self-contradictory movement that
establishes individuals. The person is self-contained, creating herself for herself alone.
Existentialist Psychoanalysis.
This essay describes how existentialism should amend Freudian psychoanalysis. Sartre
begins with similarities between existential and Freudian psychoanalysis. Each seeks to decipher
human behavior by observation. The meaning of an individual’s behaviors is unknown to the
individual. Behaviors are symbols of one’s relations to the structures that define himself. Freud,
however, sees in these symbols hidden and static sexual fixations. This unconscious complex
escapes the person and remains an enigma. Existential psychoanalysis sees the approach to
meaning of the individual. Individuals become individuals not at birth, but later, when the
individual makes the primal choices. This initial choice precedes consciousness and constitutes
the individual. It is not encrypted, but remains hidden in the open, available, with the proper
examination, to the individual. The individual must learn to see this mystery objectively, from the
point of view outside himself, of the Other. This primordial individual choice should reveal that
creating oneself leads to sympathy and action for others. Freud seeks the initial state.
Existentialists seek the initial choice. Existential psychoanalysis shows the individual his selfgenerated existence. Such a view of psychoanalysis has not yet been explained by a psychologist
of Freud’s stature.
Epitome by Brad Lancaster, © 2011. Website: lancasterlawoffice.com
Page 2 of 2.